Comments and Questions to: John Protevi
LSU French &
Italian
Protevi Home
Page
Classroom use only. Do not cite w/o permission.
Course given at University of Warwick Fall 1995
9 Sections [30-38]: not really very interesting, to be fair.
30: No Deduction of Judgment of Sublime
K: we need a deduction [justification of claim to universality and necessity] if we judge about the form of an object, as in JB, where purposiveness is based in the object;
that is, we need to justify judgment that the object appears as if it
were designed to provoke free play in us
K: but we do not need a deduction for JS [their exposition is their deduction], because what we judge purposive is not the object, but our use of the object
that is, our use is already purposive [designed to reveal superiority
of reason over sensibility {imagination}]; this superiority is the very
basis of the will [will is designed to be governed by pure practical reason];
so as internal and matching our very power of purposes, we need not justify
our use of a reflection that relies on the superiority of reason
31: Method of Deduction of Judgement of Taste
K: what we need to justify is universal validity of singular judgment
about subjective purposiveness of empirical presentation of the form of
an object; this must be a priori, not through mere "gathering votes"; thus
we have two peculiarities, to be dealth with in #32 and 33: 1) universality
of a singular judgment; 2) necessity must be a priori, but cannot be a
proof.
32: 1st Peculiarity [universality of singular J]
K: demand for autonomy of judgment: must not be imitation of others
or based on desire for approval; this raises problem of tradition: we must
have examples, but not patterns for copying; we must have guidance, yet
it must be non-conceptual.
33: 2nd Peculiarty [non-proof-based necessity]
K: no empirical basis of proof [no appeal to consensus; each JB must
be autonomous]; no a priori basis of proof [then it would be cognitive
judgment]
34: No Objective Principle of Taste
K: no concept of the beautiful can produce deductive judgements [in
other words, we can't do a determinative judgment by fitting [determining]
a particular apprehension under a pre-given universal concept to see if
the characteristics of the object fit the criteria for beauty]; rather,
"I must feel the pleasure directly"
K: nonetheless, critics can perform a useful task: investigate cognitive
powers and clarify by examples what subj purposiveness is.
K: critique of taste finds rules for [producing] free play; this is
either 1) an art: by example; 2) a science: derives possibility of free
play from nature of cognitive powers. Thus only 2), the science, is a transcendental
critique.
35: Prin Taste is Subj Prin of Power of J
K: as a judgment, JT must have a principle by which it refers a particular to a universal; but as an AJ, it must be nonconceptual, so its principle can only be subj conditions of judgment, i.e., free play of imagination [power governing particularity of intuitions] and understanding [power governing universality of concept]; this free play is what allows imagination to be subsumed under condition that allows understanding to proceed from intuition to concepts [that condition is schematism]; thus JT is based on sensation of free play/mutual animation of free imagination and lawful understanding. Thus principle of subsumtion of JT is principle that allows subsumtion of imagination under understanding [that is, harmony of freedom and lawfulness].
In other words, we judge about the conditions of judgment: we judge
judging itself.
36: Problems w/ Deduction of JT
K: this is actually the problem of transcendental philosophy as such:
how are synthetic judgments possible a priori?
37: What is asserted a priori in JT?
K: only the universal validity of the felt pleasure connected w/ judging
the object
38: Deduction of JT
K: liking is form's subj purposiveness for power of judgment [ability
to provoke free play which is condition for all judgment, since it brings
power of particularity {imagination} in tune with power of universality
{understanding}]; we can presuppose that all people have similar makeup
of their cognitive powers, for otherwise we couldn't agree, as we do in
fact do, about scientific demonstrations; we must however, remember the
proviso of purity in these judgments, that is, that we judge only the form
of the object, not any concepts or sensations concering it; nevertheless,
such a mistake is only a misapplication that doesn't threaten the right
of making the claim to universally necessary agreement
Comment
K: the deduction is easy because it doesn't need to justify objective reality of a concept [e.g., that causality applies to all possible objects of experience]. However, correct application of principle of JT [i.e., keeping JT pure of agreeableness or goodness] is "unavoidably difficult," so that mistakes are "easily made."